
What we’re about
This is a group for people who create and consume philosophy. Members will have the opportunity to read and discuss each others' work, as well as texts from pre-established philosophers. Each meeting will be partially structured, with chosen topics/texts from a rotating member; and partially un-structured, with free-form discussion.
(Note this is an in person event. An Online is posted here.) Modern Western intellectual culture has as one of its most enduring assumptions the idea that terms that relate to the mind refer to isolatable temporal states and processes of some substance. These states can be thought of as states of the body or states of an immaterial substance called the soul or the mind. For instance, one assumes that in order for someone to be angry, there is a peculiar process which goes on inside either the body or the mind, that corresponds to the term “anger” and which the term anger names. In the same way, if someone is thinking their thought is locatable either in the immmaterial substance of the mind or in some conjunction of neurons in the brain. Either way both perspectives are guided by the notion of mental terms as signifiers of processes. Both cartesian dualists, many idealists and materialists, cognitive psychologists, psychoanalysts and even many behaviorists have held this to be true.
From this straightforward conception, it is a natural idea that the mind behaves according to certain laws of action, and that there could be a special science of psychology that would study the laws of the actions of the mind, applying the methods of physical science, that is, of close observation and hypothetical reconstruction
This Point of view has certainly had its detractors, and they have, of course, made criticisms of various kinds. But perhaps no one's criticism has involved such systematic and thorough-going rejection of it as that of Ludwig Wittgenstein.
Steeped in a lifelong examination of the concept of meaning, Wittgenstein's critique of this picture begins with a consideration of the conditions under which we can speak of items having meanings. The Basic conviction arrived at from this examination is that to comprehend the meaning of words and of behavior is to comprehend the role such behavior plays in the complicated texture of a human form of life, a set of regular patterns and circumstances and activities that make up the regular activity of a group of people. Meaning in this sense is a functional holistic relation between an individual behavior or utterance and a larger, typically human pattern to which it belongs
The conclusions that he drew from this for the study of language are infamous and are embodied in such concepts as family resemblance, meaning as use, and rejection of the possibility of private languages. But they also are found to have radical implications for the understanding of psychological terminology.
For it is clear that desires, intentions, beliefs, expectations, fears, and emotions are terms that make reference to the idea of meaning. And if meaning can only be understood in terms of a symbol or behavior’s functional relation and place within regular patterns of behavior, and more generally if the meaning of a term must always have a public function, it follows that psychological terms are not primarily associated with processes happening either in the mind or the brain or even the body, but with complicated patterns of publicly observable and typically social human behavior.
If this is the case, it follows that to speak of a science of the mental processes of thinking, desiring, expecting, and willing is to speak in a fundamentally confused manner. Neither thinking nor desiring, expecting or willing is a term that refers to a mental (or physical) process at all, but rather to a complicated part whole relation between individual behaviors and complicated general families of behavioral patterns that are present in human life. To say that someone is angry or thinking or confused is not to to provide an explanation or to indicate any fact about what is going on in their mind or their body, but simply to describe the relationship between their behavior and general patterns of characteristically human behavior. Such patterns may have causal explanations, but describing the pattern is not to make any causal or substantial assumptions, but merely to classify something as a manifestation of a pattern.
In this way, Wittgenstein combines a seeming behaviorism with a kind of radical anti-reductionism and anti-positivism. There are no laws of thinking or willing because willing and thinking are not terms for processes but for complicated patterns of often socially mediated behavior whose significance lies in their functional role within human life and not in their causal regularities. It follows the proper method of understanding the human mind is not scientific explanation, but anthropological and empathetic description.
This combination of an austere rejection of grand theoretical pronouncements with a fundamentally humanistic emphasis on comprehending the complex, holistic contexts and conditions that make human action socially intelligible gives Wittgenstein's thinking a unique position among philosophies of mind, and one well worth studying.
In this Meetup, we will attempt to explore this critical and holistic vision of the mind through examination of some of the core texts of Wittgenstein's later period. Readings are linked here:
Upcoming events (4+)
See all- Aristotle's On Interpretation - Live-Reading--European StyleLink visible for attendees
September 23 - We continue reading chapter 14, the last chapter of On Interpretation. It is roughly about knowing the knowable through belief. Up until now, Aristotle has been focusing on the relationship between the knowing and the things that are known. Now, in the final chapter, he turns his attention toward the relationship between the knowing and the beliefs we craft so as to lasso-grasp the things that are known. Presently, the issue is, which belief is more opposite to the belief "A is B"; is it "A isn't B" or is it "A is C" (in which B and C are contrary concepts)? The bookmark is set at Bekker line 24a3--which is the 6th paragraph in Ackrill's translation.
.
George will read and invite us to interpret the new section.
.
The chapter review most relevant to where we are is chapter 6. Here is my review of it. https://mega.nz/file/anJBwDZZ#MKELep93ey2WkvPXkMx42dbpPL5Exa0lAs1DnYLqGek
.
Join the meeting, keep pen and notepad at the ready, and participate.
.
------
.
Organon means "instrument," as in, instrument for thought and speech. The term was given by ancient commentators to a group of Aristotle's treatises comprising his logical works.Organon
|-- Categories ---- 2023.02.28
|-- On Interpretation ---- 2023.12.12
|-- Topics ---- 2025.10.??
|-- On Sophistical Refutations
|-- Rhetoric*
|-- Prior Analytics
|-- Posterior Analytics(* Robin Smith, author of SEP's 2022 entry "Aristotle's Logic," argues that Rhetoric should be part of the Organon.)
Whenever we do any human thing, we can either do it well or do it poorly. With instruments, we can do things either better, faster, and more; or worse, slower, and less. That is, with instruments they either augment or diminish our doings.
Do thinking and speaking (and writing and listening) require instruments? Yes. We do need physical instruments like microphones, megaphones, pens, papers, computers. But we also need mental instruments: grammar, vocabulary words, evidence-gathering techniques, big-picture integration methods, persuasion strategies.
Thinking while sitting meditatively all day in a lotus position doesn't require much instrumentation of any kind, but thinking and speaking well in the sense of project planning, problem-solving, negotiating, arguing, deliberating--that is, the active doings in the world (whether romantic, social, commercial, or political)--do require well-honed mental instruments. That's the Organon in a nutshell.
Are you an up-and-coming human being, a doer, go-getter, achiever, or at least you're choosing to become one? You need to wield the Organon.
Join us.
- Lacking Self-Control -- Aristotle’s Nicomachean EthicsLink visible for attendees
September 28 - We are reading NE VII.7, which is about two variants of lacking self-control: being endurant-steadfast {karteria} and being soft-pampered {malakia}. Why does Aristotle say that these are forms of lacking self-control {akrasia}? The first sounds pretty good, right? Let's follow his train of thought.
.
We will read the 8 translations starting at 1150a9.
.
My summary of chapter 6 on lacking self-control with respect to emotion can be found here to help you catch up to us. https://mega.nz/file/OzYXXCZI#K6p6FHf2ohSrZ5NrMrr-H90w_TLYFng-kYpO4KmcHok Bring your own questions about the text if you are interested in joining this Sunday's meeting.
.
----
.
We are live-reading and discussing Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics, book VII, which is about troubleshooting the virtues of character. We use mainly the English translation by Adam Beresford (Penguin Classics, 2020).
.
The prerequisite to this book is our answering for ourselves these questions from the prior books, to which we will briefly review:
.
1. What is a virtue of character {ēthikē aretē}?
2. How does one come to acquire it? (E.g. [Aristotle’s], ambition, bravery, gentlemanliness, generosity, candor, balanced-temper, …)
3. From a first-person perspective in being virtuous, how does one feel and what does one see (differently, discursively) in a given situation of everyday living?
4. From a third-person perspective, how is the virtuous person (of a specific virtue) to be characterized?
.
.
The project's cloud drive is here, at which you'll find the reading texts, notes, and slideshows. - Aristotle's On Interpretation - Live-Reading--European StyleLink visible for attendees
Organon means "instrument," as in, instrument for thought and speech. The term was given by ancient commentators to a group of Aristotle's treatises comprising his logical works.
Organon
|-- Categories ---- 2023.02.28
|-- On Interpretation ---- 2023.12.12
|-- Topics
|-- On Sophistical Refutations
|-- Rhetoric*
|-- Prior Analytics
|-- Posterior Analytics(* Robin Smith, author of SEP's 2022 entry "Aristotle's Logic," argues that Rhetoric should be part of the Organon.)
Whenever we do any human thing, we can either do it well or do it poorly. With instruments, we can do things either better, faster, and more; or worse, slower, and less. That is, with instruments they either augment or diminish our doings.
Do thinking and speaking (and writing and listening) require instruments? Yes. We need physical instruments like microphones, megaphones, pens, papers, computers. But we also need mental instruments: grammar, vocabulary words, evidence-gathering techniques, big-picture integration methods, persuasion strategies. Thinking while sitting meditatively all day in a lotus position doesn't require much instrumentation of any kind, but thinking and speaking well in the sense of project planning, problem-solving, negotiating, arguing, deliberating--that is, the active doings in the world (whether romantic, social, commercial, or political)--do require well-honed mental instruments. That's the Organon in a nutshell.
Are you an up-and-coming human being, a doer, go-getter, achiever, or at least you're choosing to become one? You need to wield the Organon.
Join us.