
What we’re about
The Chicago Philosophy Meetup is a community of groups created by and for people interested in engagements with philosophy and the history of such engagements. Our members have a wide variety of backgrounds besides philosophy, including literature, law, physics, theology, music, and more.
We host events suggested by individual members and coordinated by volunteer organizers and offer opportunities for discussion with others who share these interests. If you have an idea for a topic you'd like to discuss, especially if you are from an historically underrepresented group in academic philosophy, let us work with you to make it happen.
Whether you're new to philosophy and looking to get started, or have been doing philosophy for some time and want to dig a bit deeper, we invite you to check us out.
We have basic expectations for how we talk to each other, so:
DO...
Listen to others
Ask for clarification
Get to know people
Help other voices to be heard
Work towards understanding each other
Practice moving past your assumptions about others
DON'T...
Limit others’ performance of items on the DO list
The Chicago Philosophy Meetup opposes any force of exclusion, discrimination, and/or harassment present in its community. Such forces include, but are not limited to, racism, transphobia, misogyny, and antisemitism. The Chicago Philosophy Meetup seeks to be inclusive because only in this way can we fulfill the DOs list above. We are here to help! If you have concerns, questions about a meeting, or need assistance (e.g. accessibility), please contact either the organizers or the event host for the meeting directly.
"Philosophy is not a theory but an activity."
-- from "Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus," Wittgenstein
Discourse cheers us to companionable
reflection. Such reflection neither
parades polemical opinions nor does it
tolerate complaisant agreement. The sail
of thinking keeps trimmed hard to the
wind of the matter.
-- from "On the Experience of Thinking," Heidegger
Check out our calendar
Upcoming events (4+)
See all- Kant: Critique of Pure Reason (Week 12)Link visible for attendees
Note: Meetings focus on developing a common language and friendship through studying Kant. The host will provide an interpretation of Kant; other interpretations will not be discussed until later in the meeting. Additional interpretations, topics, and questions can be addressed through the Jitsi chat feature.
This session will cover the Transcendental Dialectic Introduction, Book I
Online meeting link: https://meet.jit.si/CPM-Kant-Wednesdays
(links to text at bottom)
(Tentative) Schedule for Critique of Pure Reason:
Week 1:
Preface (A and B editions)
pp Avii - xxii, Bvii - xliv
pp 99 - 124 (Guyer/Wood)
pp 5 - 40 (Pluhar)Week 2:
Introduction (A and B editions)
pp A1 - 16, B1 - 30
pp 127 - 152 (Guyer/Wood)
pp 43 - 68 (Pluhar)Week 3:
Transcendental Aesthetic (A and/or B editions)
pp A19 - 49, B33 - 73
pp 155 - 192 (Guyer/Wood)
pp 71 - 104 (Pluhar)Week 4:
Transcendental Logic Introduction, Book I Chapter I
pp A50 - 83, B74 - 116
pp 193 - 218 (Guyer/Wood)
pp 105 - 140 (Pluhar)Week 5:
Transcendental Logic Chapter II 'Deduction' (A edition)
pp A84 - 130
pp 219 - 244 (Guyer/Wood)
pp 141 - 174 (Pluhar)Week 6:
Transcendental Logic Chapter II 'Deduction' (B Edition)
pp B116 - 169
pp 245 - 266 (Guyer/Wood)
pp 175 - 203 (Pluhar)Week 7:
Transcendental Logic Book II Introduction and Chapter I on the Schematism
pp A130 - 147, B169 - 187
pp 267 - 277 (Guyer/Wood)
pp 204 - 219 (Pluhar)Week 8:
Transcendental Logic Book II Chapter II
pp A148 - 176, B187 - 218
pp 278 - 295 (Guyer/Wood)
pp 220 - 247 (Pluhar)Week 9:
Analogies of Experience up to Transcendental Logic Book II Chapter III 'Phenomena and Noumena'
pp A176 - 235, B218 - 294
pp 295 - 337 (Guyer/Wood)
pp 247 - 302 (Pluhar)Week 10:
Transcendental Logic Book II Chapter III 'Phenomena and Noumena' (A and/or B editions)
pp A235 - 260, B294 - 315
pp 338 - 365 (Guyer/Wood)
pp 303 - 322 (Pluhar)Week 11:
Transcendental Logic Appendix 'Amphiboly'
pp A260 - 292, B316 - 349
pp 366 - 383 (Guyer/Wood)
pp 323 - 345 (Pluhar)Week 12:
Transcendental Dialectic Introduction, Book I
pp A293 - 340, B349 - 398
pp 384 - 410 (Guyer/Wood)
pp 346 - 381 (Pluhar)Week 13:
Transcendental Dialectic Paralogisms (A and/or B editions)
pp A341 - 405, B399 - 332
pp 411 - 458 (Guyer/Wood)
pp 382 - 441 (Pluhar)Week 14:
Transcendental Dialectic Antinomies Section I - IV
pp A405 - 484, B432 - 512
pp 459 - 507 (Guyer/Wood)
pp 442 - 501 (Pluhar)Week 15:
Transcendental Dialectic Antinomies Section V - IX
pp A485 - 567, B513 - 595
pp 508 - 550 (Guyer/Wood)
pp 502 - 559 (Pluhar)Week 16:
Transcendental Dialectic Ideal of Pure Reason
pp A567 - 642, B513 - 670
pp 551 - 589 (Guyer/Wood)
pp 560 - 616 (Pluhar)Week 17:
Appendix to Transcendental Dialectic
pp A642 - 704, B670 - 732
pp 590 - 623 (Guyer/Wood)
pp 617 - 662 (Pluhar)Week 18:
Doctrine of Method Introduction, Chapter I
pp A705 - 794, B733 - 822
pp 627 - 671 (Guyer/Wood)
pp 663 - 727 (Pluhar)Week 19:
Doctrine of Method Chapter II
pp A795 - 830, B823 - 858
pp 672 - 690 (Guyer/Wood)
pp 728 - 755 (Pluhar)Week 20:
Doctrine of Method Chapter III and IV
pp A832 - 856, B860 - 884
pp 691 - 704 (Guyer/Wood)
pp 755 - 774 (Pluhar)Two different translations are recommended - both are good:
Preserves original sentence structure: Guyer/Wood
Updates for readability: PluharLinks to the text:
PDF of Guyer/Wood translation:
https://libgen.li/edition.php?id=136607414EPUB of Guyer/Wood translation:
https://libgen.li/edition.php?id=137975974PDF of Pluhar translation:
https://libgen.li/edition.php?id=136394041Buy the book on Amazon (or find it someplace else if you don't like Amazon):
Guyer/Wood:
https://www.amazon.com/Critique-Reason-Cambridge-Works-Immanuel/dp/0521657296/ref=sr_1_3Pluhar (All three Critiques):
https://www.amazon.com/Three-Critiques-3-Set-Practical/dp/0872206297/ref=sr_1_3Pluhar hardcovers recommended (if available): https://www.amazon.com/Three-Critiques-3-Set-Practical/dp/0872206300/ref=sr_1_2
- Kant FTΦ: Leibniz' Twenty-Four Statements (presented by Heidegger)Link visible for attendees
Meeting link: https://meet.jit.si/CPM-Kant-Wednesdays
We'll start on page 52 with statement 17. (We are on our second trip through the statements.)
The immediate goal of these meetings is to work towards a philosophical interpretation of Leibniz with the interest of eventually bringing this reading into comparison with Kant. This will require a study of Leibniz. To first lead us into this study we will begin with a work of Heidegger's: "Metaphysics as History of Being" from the collection "The End of Philosophy". This essay will ultimately present a pivotal role that Leibniz' thought has in the history of metaphysics. It will first build a background for understanding Leibniz' role through a presentation of figures such as Aristotle and Descartes. At the end of the essay, a short work of Leibniz' is presented, his "twenty-four statements".
Book on Amazon: https://www.amazon.com/End-Philosophy-Martin-Heidegger/dp/0226323838
PDF: https://annas-archive.org/md5/b13b7532e83b37f4d3e1c8aa1521e9a3
Note: Kant FTΦ (Friends Through Philosophy) is a group of individuals who have connected over reading Kant (and other philosophers). New attendees are welcome, but please observe silently during the meeting. You may use the Jitsi chat feature to participate.
This meeting will focus on individual FTΦ participants' interests, with frequent references to Kant and other philosophers. Discussions may involve shared notions developed over time.
- Heidegger: Being and Time (Week 8)Oak Park Public Library - Main Library, Oak Park, IL
In Being and Time, Heidegger aims to reawaken our sense for the question, 'What does it mean to be?'. We can be said to have forgotten what this question asks, not because it isn't important, but because the language we might use to talk about this question papers over what we wanted to address. It is the question—not the answer—which is sought after here.
But because the question, 'What does it mean to be?', is inherently intertwined with the concerns and affairs of she who raises it, Heidegger turns to analyze what it is like for us to be there, or to concern ourselves with what it means to be. Being and Time thus considers what it is like for things to matter to us every day, the ways in which meaningfulness can utterly collapse or fail, and just how difficult it is for us to understand and commit ourselves in a way that is our own.
Whether you're new to discussing philosophical texts or can paraphrase Heidegger's later work, we'd be happy to have you join in the new year!
Join us every other Thursday at 6!
**Reading schedule:
- Introduction I: §§1–4
- Introduction II: §§5–8
- Part 1, Division 1, I–II: §§9–13
- III: §§14–18 (stop at B)
- III: §§18B–24
- IV: §§25–27
- V: §§28–33
- V: §§34–38
- VI: §§39–42
- VI: §§42–44
- Part 1, Division 2, I: §§45–53
- II: §§54–60
- III: §§61–66
- IV: §§67–68
- IV: §§69–71
- V: §§72–77
- VI: §§78–83
Purchase the John Macquarie and Edward Robinson translation or the revised translation by Joan Stambaugh.
- From Socrates to Sartre EP13 ⟩ “Hume II: ‘A Well-Meanin’ Critter’”Link visible for attendees
These, the best overview lectures of all time, provide a complete college course in philosophy. Beginners will get clarity and adepts will be revitalized.
Thelma Zeno Lavine’s From Socrates to Sartre: The Philosophic Quest (1978) is the most riveting (her painstaking contortionist elocution), endearing (the eerie, theremin-laced Moog soundtrack, straight from the golden age of PBS), and confrontational (her radical politics and censorship-defying critiques) philosophy lecture series ever produced.
Hume Part II; or, how to atomize philosophy into sense-data and rebuild it as psychology, so that the art formerly known as metaphysics is exposed as mental habit
David Hume’s mom described him as “a well-meanin’ critter, but uncommon weak-minded.” As everyone knows, that description could not be more ironic. Hume matured into the second-sharpest British philosopher and the fourth greatest Western philosopher of all time (according to Leiter’s 2017 poll).
While his family thought he was dutifully studying law, Hume was secretly immersed in philosophy. The breakthrough came when he absorbed the work of Francis Hutcheson’s claim that ethical principles actually have subjective feeling(rather than divine command or rational insight) as their basis.
Hume’s radical and epoch-making move was to extend Hutcheson’s subjective feeling-ism to cover the domain of all knowledge generally.
If Kant was wakened by Hume’s attack on causality, Hume awoke through Hutcheson’s recognition that reason never wasthe author of moral truth, only its rationalizing scribe.
What an absolutely exhilarating and totally reasonable and intelligible simplifying model Hutcheson had proposed! Hume called Hutcheson’s extension of empiricism and the Newtonian method into epistemology, metaphysics, and morality—and the reduction of all three to psychological laws—the new “Scene of Thought”. It propelled Hume into intellectual ecstasy.
In fact, the revelation was so exciting that Hume gave up law (which he’d started studying at age 12 ) and worked instead on the new scene—and so entered a six-month long manic episode buzzing with discovery, breakthrough, and feelings of great power.
Hume’s exhilarating new philosophical outlook fused the empiricism of Locke and Berkeley—who held that all knowledge derives from sense perception—with the moral philosophy of Francis Hutcheson, who argued that morality rests not on reason or revelation, but on sentiment. Hume’s breakthrough lay in extending Hutcheson’s insight beyond ethics: if moral belief arises from feeling rather than reason, then perhaps all belief—even in the sciences—does as well. On this view, so-called scientific knowledge is not grounded in objective certainty, but in our feeling that repeated sensory patterns can be trusted as truth.
But the exhilaration of his breakthrough soon gave way to anxiety and dread. In 1729, Hume suffered a severe nervous collapse, followed by five years of what we would now call clinical depression.
Convinced that his philosophical ambitions were doomed, he resolved to abandon philosophy altogether.
Yet within months, he reversed course and retreated to La Flèche, the site of Descartes’s old Jesuit college, where he feverishly composed his Treatise of Human Nature (1739).
In Praise of Reductionism
Confession time: We all love reductionism. Who doesn’t want the chaos of the total experience situation boiled down to a few elegant principles? We want personality types, root causes, five love languages, the single trauma that explains everything. The sciences, of course, also run on this fuel. Kant called it a regulative love, because intelligibility and derivability from one (or a few) covering laws just is the inner life of understanding.
What makes the application of “the Newtonian method” to the nature of the internal experiencing machine different from the previous attempts at mechanical reductions, by Hobbes and Descartes?
Before Newton, Hobbes attempts to reduce human action to motion and desire (Leviathan, 1651). He explicitly models reasoning as calculation and the passions as mechanistic effects of appetite and aversion.
Descartes, in the Passions of the Soul (1649), attempts a neuro-mechanical account of emotion. But Hobbes and Descartes are still working from rationalist metaphysical premises—they posit mechanistic accounts, but they lack Newton’s empirical framework.
It is only with Locke that the method matures into something like a proper “doctrine of elements.” Locke’s Essay is the first great attempt to reduce mental operations to a finite set of faculties (sensation, reflection, comparison, etc.), with ideas built up from sense data. He rejects innate ideas and insists on an empirical model of the mind, but he is not yet modeling the mind as governed by laws in the Newtonian sense.
The Humean Anthropological Turn
Hume will reduce human mental life to a few simple principles. But why is he going to do this? It is because all other sciences are based upon the science of man. Therefore to study the science of man, the science of human nature, is really to study the foundation of all human knowledge. The idea is simple: since all access to reality is mediated by the mind, a systematic account of how the mind operates offers, in principle, a synoptic understanding of the conditions under which reality becomes knowable at all. The study of human nature is actually a metacritical study of all knowability generally.
Hume begins his Treatise with a modest taxonomy: all contents of consciousness are either impressions (lively, sensory, immediate) or ideas (fainter copies derived from impressions). From there, he develops an argument:
- Every meaningful idea must be traceable to a prior impression.
- If no such impression can be found, the idea is meaningless.
- Therefore, metaphysical notions—substance, mind, self—turn out to be empty shells, linguistic husks inherited from tradition but devoid of empirical content.
In the Enquiry (1748), this becomes not just an epistemic principle but a criterion of meaning, similar to the later empiricist semantic verificationism of Ayer and the logical positivists. Hume’s rule is simple, brutal, and final: no impression, no idea; no idea, no meaning.
And with that, centuries of rationalist metaphysics are swept aside.
Hume does not stop at demolishing metaphysics. He reconceives the very mechanism of thought. The mind, in his view, does not reason in the traditional sense—it associates. Impressions and their ideas are atomistic, discrete, and inert, unless animated by three “gentle forces”: resemblance, contiguity, and cause-effect. These psychological principles—not logic—explain how we move from one idea to another, even in science.
Of these, causation is the most consequential. And it is here that Hume’s assault on Enlightenment rationality is most devastating.
Science as Feeling
Scientific knowledge, Hume argues, rests on causal inference. But we never perceive causal necessity; we only perceive constant conjunctions—fire regularly followed by heat, wounds followed by pain.
There is a glueiness of the mind that puts them together when the same impression is repeated often enough. It doesn’t come up through logical necessity. It comes from … somewhere else. For Hume, the womb of these apparently in-world connections is our own expectational feeling. The feeling of outer necessity is just that—a feeling, born of custom.
The upsetting conclusion: the laws of physics are not objective features of nature but subjective psychological habits. What we call science is simply an ordering of impressions through mental association, accompanied by a sentiment of compulsion.
In other words, as Thelma so pungently puts it, physics is psychology. Newton’s laws, the crown jewels of Enlightenment reason, are demoted to complex regularities we happen to expect. A nightmare for scientific realists and all normals generally.
Bonus Observation: Hume as Proto-Kantian Rationalist
In addition to tracing the standard destroyer narrative, we’ll also explore Hume’s incipient metaphysical constructivism. While Hume never explicitly endorsed a second kind of necessity, he noted mind’s innate ability to lock onto causal patterns in nature. It’s just that his explanations of what the causation amounts to had to do with the mind projecting itself onto those non-coincidental unities, something he was not inclined to call necessary.
If Hume stopped short of calling this “necessity,” Kant would not: Here, Kant might have said, is the missing piece—a form of necessity rooted in the mind’s ability to recognize non-coincidental regularities through perception, imagination, and innate spatiotemporal structure.
Hume thus occupies a position far closer to Kant than the traditional narrative allows. His empiricism, once expanded to include memory, imagination, and the mind’s structuring activity, begins to look less like skepticism and more like a mitigated rationalism.
If rationalism is all about defending the formal sciences and the natural sciences—and modal grounds of both—then Hume is, in that sense, a rationalist.
This arc—from Locke through Hume to Kant—can be seen as the gradual emergence of a theory of non-logical necessity, grounded in primary qualities and the mind’s capacity to track them. Locke’s search for the mental faculties that correspond to nature’s objective structure anticipates Kant’s claim that experience is intelligible only because the world must conform to the forms of our judgment. Hume occupies the inflection point: a proto-structuralist of sensibility whose analysis of causal connection—though framed in terms of habit and feeling—exposed the need for a deeper account of the mind’s role in constituting necessity. In doing so, he provided the very problem-structure that would allow Kant to reconceive metaphysics on new, transcendental grounds.
METHOD
Please watch the tiny 27-minute episode before the event. We will then replay a few short clips during the event for debate and discussion. A version with vastly improved audio can be found here:
Summaries, notes, event chatlogs, episode transcripts, timelines, tables, observations, and downloadable PDFs (seek the FSTS Book Vault) of the episodes we cover can be found here:
ABOUT PROFESSOR LAVINE
Dr. Lavine was professor of philosophy and psychology as Wells College, Brooklyn College, the University of Maryland (10 years), George Washington University (20), and George Mason University (13). She received the Outstanding Faculty Member award while at the University of Maryland and the Outstanding Professor award during her time at George Washington University.
She was not only a Dewey scholar, but a committed evangelist for American pragmatism.
View all of our coming episodes here.